Images and their relatives : Introduction (draft) (Paul Dumouchel)
I am
interested by what may be described as the semantic cloud surrounding the
concept of images. What I mean by a semantic cloud may be illustrated with the
help of a kanji – the ideograms of Chinese origin which the Japanese use to
write their language. Because of the structure of Japanese language kanjis are
not usually alone but associated with phonetic signs – hiragana syllabary – they
form different words and in these words the kanji – the Chinese ideogram – constitutes
or indicates the root meaning of the words in which it enters. Take for example
the following kanji “shita”* which means below, as in
“you will find it below the table”. That kanji enters into the following words,
among others: below, down, please, to hang (a painting), to be under guidance,
to give, to be unskilful, to surrender, to be discharged, to get down the
train, to give an order, to make a judgement, to be inferior, to fall back, to
receive, urine, diarrhea, the lower part of a river, to be downwind,
subordinate, and subcontractor. We can stop here.
All these
words are in some way related to the fact of being lower in space and to the
idea of inferiority (physical or political) and of what has less value. A kanji
like shita can be understood as being as the center of a semantic cloud, a set
of words which are semantically related. The relation between these terms is
not etymological. It is not one of historical descent, but one of meaning, or
rather meanings, because there are many different meaning relations between the
various terms in the writing of which the kanji “shita” enters. These relations
are fuzzy and manyfold. They are not clear like deduction, neither are they
linear like descent, nor is it a set of arbitrary associations. That is why I
call this a semantic cloud, a cloud of meanings whose contour is not very clear
and well defined, but whose center is the fact of being below and the idea of inferiority.
Another
aspect of this example which I think is important is that it involves two very
different components. First to be below or under in physical space, which is
not an idea, but a fact. It is something or an event in the world that you
observe or perceive. “The garbage bin is underneath the sink.” Second,
inferiority in various relations, which is not a material thing that is
directly physically observable but something that has to do with thought and
meaning. This semantic cloud associates two very different elements, a state of
affairs in the world and an idea or concept, that of being inferior which
extends to the domain of value.
In languages
which are written phonetically we cannot recognize semantic clouds as easily,
simply by looking for the root kanji. A semantic cloud is a cluster of concepts
or ideas that are related together through their meaning and I think that we
can recognize a semantic cloud when we find a group of ideas that are related
in such a way that we tend to explain any member of that group in relation to
other members. That I believe is the case of images, ideas, representation,
copy, reproduction, imitation, simulation, icons, mirror or mirroring, figuring,
mimesis, and model are related in this way and they form a semantic cloud. It
is, for example, hard to explain what is representation without taking about
images, ideas, copies or reproduction and vice versa it is hard to explain what
is an idea without using referring to a copies, representations or images. My
claim is that it is image that sits at the center of this semantic cloud, image
is in this case the equivalent of the root kanji. All these ideas have a visual
dimension or connotation which is more than suggested by the importance of the
resemblance between two objects or behavior. A resemblance that is visual and
can be perceived that offers itself as a criteria or the means of recognizing[1] that we are dealing with a
copy, an imitation, mirror image, etc.
Of course,
very early on in the Western philosophical tradition attempts will be made to sunder
the relationship between visual and non-visual representation, between images
and ideas – the word “eikon” in ancient Greek was originally used for both. However,
the temptation of understanding representation as essentially visual will never
disappear and will repeatedly become dominant for a while. In fact, whenever we
try to explain the ideas of representation, of model, of copy or reproduction a
visual metaphor is never far away. Or better, it seems that many these terms have
both a visual and a non-visual interpretation. This is evident in such terms as
model, representation, simulation, reproduction, figuring and mimesis.
These different
notions – images, imitation or simulation – are also closely related to the
phenomena of dreams, to imagination and to visions – understood in this last
case not as a form of perception but as a revelation or visitation from another
world. Simulation, reproduction, imitation, copies and images are also sometime
related to what is false and to deceit, but they are also associated to the opposite,
to truth and to what reveals the world as it is. In fact, the debate concerning
whether images, ideas, representation, models and imitation reveals or deceive
is never completely separated from the question of whether we should understand
these ideas visually or not.
Finally
images are central to how we understand or represent thinking and knowing. This
is the case since Plato’s theory of ideas (eikon) – the Greek word for images –
to the central role and importance of representations in todays cognitive
science. In consequence, our inability to escape this semantic cloud when
trying to explain one or another of its concepts, our failure to explain them in
relation to something that is completely different is somewhat troubling, as if
we reaching here some kind of limit.
Clearly
related, but, I think, members of a different semantic clouds are the ideas of
sign, symbol, writing, calculating, and again but this time differently the
notions of metaphors and of figures of style. These, I believe, do not belong
to the same cluster of ideas as images and representation. Though as we will
see later on they may be considered as descending from it. The main difference
between the two types of objects (images and their relatives on the one hand,
signs, symbols and numbers on the other) concerns the role of rules of
composition between them. What I mean is that though art historians for
examples will explain to us the rule of composition of various painting, there
are no rules of composition between paintings while words and numbers derive
their force essentially through syntax and rules.
Something
similar, I think, applies to models and simulations. There is a grammar that applies
within a model or simulation but not easily between different one. A model or
simulation, like an image is an independent object or reality. Each one forms a
whole and individual, while signs and numbers function in community. In that
sense, the ideograms of non-phonetically written languages which represent one
complete idea would in a sense be in between an image and a sign.
So I am
interested in the group, cloud or cluster of notions and objects mentioned
above, let us call it: images. One observation and a multiple hypothesis guide
my interest and inquiry. The observation first: Images, ideas, copy,
reproduction, representation, imitation, simulation, icons, mirroring, dreams, mimesis
and models all participate in two different paradigms.[2] The first paradigm is
identity. That is a copy, an image, a representation, a simulation, an icon or
imitation should as much as possible be “like” or truthful to that of which it
is a copy, an image, a representation, simulation, imitation of. Perfection in
imitation appears as the goal to be aimed at. And images understood in relation
to this paradigm are related to truth which is itself conceived as a perfect representation
or adequate image of reality, of what is. This paradigm leads to the following paradox.
Perfection in imitation or resemblance, as well as complete truth, abolishes
the idea of imitation or resemblance. What we are dealing with when perfect
reproduction is achieved is not an image anymore, not a copy, nor
representation, but another one of the same, a second hat, house or person, not
an image but reality. A copy that is a perfect imitation is not a copy anymore
but one more individual, another token of the same class, or the same individual
the thing itself that was for a moment confused with its image. – the example
of bronze sculptures.
Magritte’s
famous painting « Ceci est une
pipe » trades on this particular ambiguity, which introduces us to the second
paradigm.
The second
paradigm is that of difference. An image, idea, model, representation or
simulation is always different from what it is an image, idea, model,
representation or simulation of. The two cannot be identical. The image is a
different object and reality than what it is an image of, which in art theory
is often called its prototype, and this difference is not viewed as an
imperfection, as in the first paradigm, but as precisely what makes an image
and image. What makes a painting a good painting or a sculpture a good
sculpture is the artist’s success in making “the same”, in reproducing or
copying the paradigm but in a completely different material.
In this
case, it is the difference, between the image and what it is an image of, that is
precisely what is important, useful, and fruitful. Here the ontological horizon
of representation is not for the copy to disappear in the original, or for
reality to supersede the function of image. What is fundamental is the
appearance of reality and the appearance (or emergence) of a new type of
objects: images, representations, models, simulations, that represent the world
as it is, so to speak, but that are not what they represent, that are
different. These are objects that did not exist before, objects that are made
on purpose to represent (they are not natural objects) and that, unlike different
tokens of the same class and unlike the prototype of the image, belong to an
entirely different type of realities.
In the case
of the first paradigm, imitation is thought ideally or in its most perfect form
to lead to the collapse of the difference between the imitator and the imitated,
and the image’s failure to do that is viewed as a mistake or failure or at
least as an imperfection. – There are Chinese legends of painted birds that
take flight. The greatest artist is one who reproduces reality so well that the
animals and plants that he paints become alive. According to the second
paradigm, the image, imitation, simulation or model asserts the difference that
separates its from the original and builds on it. What gives modelling and in
many case drawing its advantage is that it is different from its prototype,
though it needs in some sense to be “like it”. What makes a mime all dressed in
white a great mime is that we can recognize different characters through his
mimics.
The tension
and hesitation between these two paradigms of images is present throughout the
whole semantic cloud and throughout the history of art. Images,
representations, simulations, imitations, and dreams are evaluated, sometimes
positively, sometimes negatively, depending on whether they are more “like” or
more “different” from what they represent, whether they are real or appearances.
At times similarity is praised and valued at other times, it is difference that
is prized and pursued. This hesitation between the value of identity or
difference is related to how we understand truth.
The
hypothesis is more difficult to present. At this point it is constituted of a
set of (at least) three different hypotheses which it may be later possible to
unite into one only, but for now I do not know how to do that.
1 The first
hypothesis is that the differences between the two paradigms are in some way
related to the difference between imitation and mimesis, both of them
considered as actions rather than as the result of action. In other words how
is the action of imitating different from being mimetic. There are many
differences between mimesis and imitation, but two in particular are worth
noticing in this context. One is that imitation essentially is a dyadic
relation while mimesis is a triadic relation and this is also the case of images
which fundamentally are triadic relations. Images are triadic in two senses.
First the images establishes a relation with its viewer and with its content.
So that there are three things involved here: the image of the tree, the tree
and the person looking at the image. Second, an image is made by someone and
looked at by someone else, or maybe by the same person at a different time. There
are three poles involved, the person who makes the image, the object (or
prototype) of which the image is the image, and the person who looks at the
image. Images are made for others or for a later incarnation of myself, an
other in that sense. The image also has a purpose, which is to be seen.
Note,
because that will become important later on, that this triadic relation does
not exist in the case of what we call mental images or representations. My
mental images or representations are for me, they are not for someone else, and
they are not made on purpose by anyone. They arise spontaneously and from
ancient Greek philosophy to today, they are conceived as establishing a dyadic
relation between the agent who has the image and the world.
When I see
an image of a tree or of a pipe, I can look at a tree or a pipe and compare the
prototype with the image. This is something that I cannot do in the case of
mental images or representations. In the case of a mental image because when I
look at the tree the mental image is not there and vice versa when I inspect my
mental image of a tree, I cannot observe the tree. In the case of mental
representation the difficulty is really the same though it present itself differently.
Given that my mental representations are assumed to be the way I know or relate
to the world, it is impossible for me to interact with a tree otherwise than
through my mental representation of a tree, in consequence my relation to the
world is condemned to remain dyadic. Both the relation between the
representations and the world and between me and my representation is dyadic
are dyadic and unlike what is the case of an image there is no way for the
relation to ever become triadic.
However, if
both mimesis and images are triadic relation, mimesis, as we will see later on,
is continuous and dynamic, while images are static and discrete. Even though films,
dreams and video games may seem to escape these limitations they in fact do
not. The reason why such moving images fail to become dynamic the mimesis is
because images are always framed. They have a frame, box, or magic circle that
imprisons them and out of which they cannot escape. That is to say, like ritual
actions, images give themselves as separated from normal life. Images are
objects, but they are a very specific type of objects. And perhaps that in a
sense, the goal and purpose of images is precisely to arrest and stop the flow
of life.
Note that
if this explanation is correct it suggest that to be dynamic you need to be
continuous. Models, like ABM models, where time is discrete suggests the same.
Hypothesis
1): the fact that images are triadic relations indicates that they are more
related to mimesis than to imitation. (I will have to explain in a clearer way what
this means or entails and this will be the topic of the second conference.)
2 The
second, closely related, hypothesis is that difference between the image or the
copy, and the prototype is grounded in the material dimension of the image or copy.
This corresponds to a certain point to what the art historian Hans Belting*
calls the medium.[3]
An image is always realized in a medium of some sort, paint on a canvas, stone,
or flashes of light and colour on a digital screen. And one of the defining
characteristics of an image is that its matter, its medium, is different from
the matter of the prototype. If it were the same we would fall into the earlier
mentioned paradox where it would not be an image, but another example of the
same.
We
sometimes say of a child that he or she is the prefect image of his father or
her of her mother, but that is a figure of speech, a child is not an image. It
is important that the copy, image or representation, should exist as an object
that is different from and exists independently of both what is copied and of
the image maker.
This point suggests
an interesting objection. If it is true that a copy in order to be an image
must be made of a different matter than what it is a copy of, doesn’t it follow
that mechanically reproduced images are not images? In fact no. The answer to
this apparent paradox is that mechanically reproduced copies of an image which
are made of the same matter as the original image are not images of what they
are a copy of. That is to say, a print that is made from a previous print,
copied from it in such a way that it is a print of the similar kind as the
original is an image, but it is not an image of the first print. It is an image
of whatever the first print is an image of.
The requirement
that images be material and of a material that is different from the material
that constitutes the prototype implies that mental images or dreams only really
become images when they are related to something that is different from both
the dreamer and the dream itself. To put is otherwise, the fact that we are
dealing with an image or representation rather than with another token of the
same is equivalent to saying that the representation exists as a concrete
particular and as an object of a different type from both the object of which
it is a copy and the copier. This a sense repeats what was said in describing the
imaging relation as triadic rather than simply dyadic.
This
autonomy and reality of the image disappears when the imitation does not give
rise to an object that is different from both the imitator and the imitated.
This, as noted before, is the case with mental images, which is another way of
saying that mental representations are private, rather than public. To the
opposite, images because they are material objects that are distinct from both
the imitator and the imitated are public. They are there to be seen by anyone
who cares to look, not hidden inside the agent’s head.
Hypothesis
2): Images are material objects. They are concrete particular. This may seem
evident but it is often overlooked. Here I want to insist on the difference
between images as such and other type of (pseudo)visual representation.
3 The third,
again closely related, hypothesis concerns current cognitive science which views
representations as central to knowledge and cognition. Cognitive science
postulates that all cognitive systems have (or contain) internal representations
that allow them to be cognitive systems. My suspicion is that when cognitive
science is understood in this way, it naïvely views internal “representations”
as if they were images. That is to say, as if they were material objects that
are distinct from both what they represent and from the representer. Mainstream
cognitive science tends to endow internal representations with the
characteristics of images, and to understands cognition as if it were
represented somewhat in the same way as external representations, in the way images
relate to the objects in the world. As copies or doubles of the world, but
copies that have no substance.
Hypothesis
(2) implies that such a view of internal representation and knowledge is
incorrect, mental representations are not images. My claim then is that
representations are only images to the extent that they are material objects of
a different type than the object they represent and of the representer. Purely
ideal, mathematical or digital representations as such are not images either
because they are not objects or the right type of objects. In consequence, they
tend to collapse into identity, as is implicit in the claim that all is data. The
representation is the world says that claim. There is, I want to argue, a
certain inescapable concreteness to the relation of representation, in the
sense that a representation is something different from that of which it is a
representation and different from the representer.
Hypothesis
3): only images are true representation because a representation is a material
object that is different from both the representer and the represented
This third
hypothesis, if it is true, suggest the following claim: that while representations
in terms of images play a fundamental role in human cognition and knowledge,
but this role, the central place of images and representation in human
knowledge is not found in the way most cognitive systems work, not even the way
large parts of human cognitive abilities function. Images have shaped our
cognitive system in a way we do not find in other cognitive systems.
The usual
claim would be that it is because humans have a different, more evolved or developed
cognitive system that they make image, the claim I want to defend is the
converse. It is because humans make images that they have a more evolved or
developed cognitive system. When I say “make images”, “make” should be
understood in a very wide sense, perhaps it would be best to say, it is because
humans trade in images that they have a more developed cognitive system.
We live in
a world that is full of images, that contains so many images that we fail to
notice it. But we do not fail to notice the images.
Underlying
this claim is, among others, the following observation. Humans are the only
animals who make images, and images – beginning with cave drawings and
handprints – have been with us since the beginning of modern humans. However,
all animals, all cognitive systems are deemed to rest on representations,
including artificial ones. This raises the question: why don’t they make images,
or to put it otherwise, why do we make images and what does that have to do with
our particular cognitive abilities? What is the point or advantage of these
external representations?
That is, how
do representations that are a different physical object from that of which they
are representations and yet in some way similar to them affect our knowledge of
the world? Internal representations, to the extent that they may be considered
as material objects, are fleeting distributed processes not concrete particular
as images are and they are not objects for the agent who has these representations.
They are not for him or her who has these representation objects, that person
does not experiences them as mental images of the world but as the world. When you see a tree what you experience is a
tree, not a mental image of a tree which the neurologist or philosopher say is
what you really are in contact with. And when the neurologist views them as
objects, i.e. patterns of neural activity, he or she does not experience them
as images. If the central hypothesis of present cognitive science is correct, if
all cognition rests on “mental representation”, why were we not satisfied with them?
What do painting, drawing, carving add to or reveal about our cognitive
abilities? How did images transform us as cognitive systems?
I do not
know the answer to these questions but I think they are worth asking. All three
hypotheses are still vague and need to be developed. In many ways this course
is the opportunity of doing that. However, at this point all of this is rather abstract,
abstruse philosophy and cognitive science. How can I transform this into a
palatable course for students who are not philosophers or cognitive scientists
– which in many ways is a good thing, because students of philosophy and
cognitive sciences tend to already be “deformed” by the dominant paradigms in
these disciplines, which in spite of what is often claimed tend to fuse together
images and mental images. Their main way of rejecting this accusation is by
saying that representation should not be understood as if it were visual representation.
That however is a very old issue and centuries of philosophy have not succeeded
in coming out clear about it. The point I want to insist on is not the visual
or non visual representation, but its material dimension.
8 courses or conferences
1 Introduction
This is what we have just done, my
goal here was to present the general problematic of images, describe what I see
as some of their fundamental characteristics, and indicates how they relate to
some other concepts especially those of representation and mental image. The 7
talks that follow can be considered as independent from each other, and there
will be some overlap and repetition. However, they are nonetheless related and
there is a certain progression between them. In other words, you do not have to
follow them all, but I will, because the different talks are not unrelated and
they will respond to each other.
2 Mimesis
and imitation*
Here I will present some fundamental
aspects of René Girard mimetic theory. First I will give an overview of the
theory insisting on some consequences of this way of looking at the world,
among other thing the importance if gives to violence, that are consequential
for the way I want to analyse images. In particular, I will stress the difference
between imitation and mimesis. At this point I will not talk so much about
images but about what I think underlies the ability to make images.
3 The power
of images*
First, I will review and expand on
some of things I said about images in the first meeting. After I will analyse
to example that illustrate the power of images. Humans respond to images in
very forceful ways. The two examples of the power or images, I will present
illustrate two different relations between images and violence. First, how we
do violence with images: revenge porn and second, how we do violence to images:
iconoclasm
4 Robots
and images*
Most social robots are made in our
image Sometimes extremely so, for example robots like Gemenoid or Sophia that
are doubles of real person in the first case. Sometimes, they only vaguely
resemble us, but for various robots we will look at most social robots have a
humanoid shape and aim to imitate various aspects of human behaviour. Are such
robots images? The answer, I will suggest has something to do with the notion
of presence which is fundamental in both robotics and the analysis of images.
5 Icons,
Index and Symbols*
The American philosopher Charles
Sandor Peirce distinguishes between three different types of signs: icons,
indexes, and symbols. Icons are images, but symbols are not. It is not entirely
clear where indexes stand in relation to images. The anthropologist Alfred Gell
proposes an anthropology of theory of art that analyses all works of arts as
indexes. Most of the art works he has in mind is not representative and I will
argue that indexes are the paradigm of non-representative images.
6 Copies
and Models: Reproduction and originals*
Here we will turn in part towards
biology where copying and reproduction play such an important role, but also to
the idea of modelization in science. In biology one of the main issue is the
fidelity of the copying process, its exactness and conversely copying mistake. And
the result of this copying process is not an image but another one of the same,
another protein, another cell, another complex organism. Evolutionary biology,
or rather evolution can be seen as a series of copying mistake. – distinguish
between biological reproduction and industrial reproduction.
In science modelizing is guided by a completely
different set of criteria. A model by definition disregards many important aspects
of whatever it aims at modelling. The gain in knowledge a model can provide is
closely related to the fact that the model is an imperfect representation. (To
take an excessively evident example, we modelize thermos-nuclear reactions
because such models are not thermos-nuclear reactions.) The importance
of the difference between the model and what it is a model of remains true even
in the sciences of artificial that use the synthetic method: learning by doing
7 Ideas,
images, representations and intentional objects*
It is probably no accident that in
so many languages to see also means to understand and, in English at least, to
understand is also said “to figure”. In fact, the Greek word eidos from
which is derived our word “idea” also means form, figure and image. So, I wish
to enquire into the relationship between vision and understanding, between
seeing and grasping (another, but different, interesting image!), between
figure and figuring. I also wish to address the relationship between images, which
are concrete particulars, and abstract concept, classes. Representation is a
central concept in cognitive sciences that is inseparable from the idea of an
intentional object, which is more or less viewed as a mental image which the
subject uses to act in the world. According to this point of view, we do not
interact with the world but with a mental image of the world. An image however,
is not an intentional object, but an object in the world that represents by
being both like and different from the object it represents. Images, I will
argue are the model of intentional objects. It is images that provided us with
that idea.
8. Do we
live in a simulation?*
There is a suggestion that has been
advanced by some philosophers, but also by others, i.e. Elon Musk, or the film Matrix
that we live in a simulation. This idea has a long and sophisticated ancestry
in philosophy which I will review rapidly. I will argue that this hypothesis is
inseparable from reducing representation to a dyadic relation and confusing
representations with images.
[1] Note that “seeing” and “recognizing” are also more or less
interchangeable so that explaining one by the other again is to some extent
explaining the same by the same!
[2][2] The opposition between these two paradigms constitutes the
beginning thesis of Quatremère de Quincy Essai sur la nature, les buts et
les moyens de l’imitation dans les beaux-arts, 1823.
[3] H.
Belting, Anthropologie des images, Paris : Gallimard, 2008.
Comments
Post a Comment